Review

The Apples of Cézanne

David Carrier 

T. J. Clark, If These Apples Should Fall: Cézanne and the Present. Thames & Hudson, 240pp., $40.

After I read and reviewed T. J. Clark’s important new book, I wanted to test his claims against some of the artworks that it describes. And so I went to see the Cezanne retrospective at the Tate Modern, London.[1]

Eleven galleries of the Tate Modern are devoted to this exhibition. It opens with the juxtaposition of Portrait of the Artist with Pink Background (1875) with The Packet of Apples (1893), a nice demonstration of the variety of his art. In that self-portrait he eyes us warily, his face set above the dark overcoat, which is so massive as to be an anticipation, almost, of his images of Mont Sainte-Victoire. What in the world is the design in pink on the wall behind him? And in the still life, the big bowl of apples at the left is precariously poised above the white tablecloth, on a table whose left and right edges do not even aspire to match. We then get a marvelous presentation of Cezanne’s early proto-expressionist works. I was especially fascinated by The Eternal Feminine (1877), with the men, including one figure with a cardinal’s red robe and a bishop’s miter, who is he?, gaping at the triumphant nude woman. On the right, one man turned towards her seems to be painting a landscape. And beneath him there are blaring trumpets. And then there are on display numerous still lives, landscapes and burly female nudes and muscular male body builders. Particularly strange is the tightly composed group, Five Bathers (1885-87), the women in an overlapping pattern making weird hand gestures. And of special interest is Three Bathers (1876-77), a picture long owned by Henri Matisse, who was much inspired by this work. Cezanne was not always successful—sometimes he went too far. Mont Saint-Victoire (1902-6) and Mont Saint-Victore Seen from Les Lauves (1904-6), for example, are over-painted, which produces a murky effect not unlike that of some Joan Mitchell’s less unsuccessful abstractions.

If you’re to understand Cezanne’s marginal artworld status which remained important through most of his lifetime, then it’s important to consider a claim that will surprise most present day viewers. To most early critics and even to many fellow late nineteenth-century artists, he seemed simply to be an incompetent painter. And, in context, that judgment wasn’t crazy. In his still lives, the left and right edges of the tabletops don’t match. With their heavy outlined edges, many of his apples don’t look like apples. Cezanne’s nudes are generally monstrous. And his portraits don’t depict their subjects in a conventionally satisfying manner. In short, Cezanne just couldn’t get things right. However eccentric were some of Edgar Degas’ motifs, no one could doubt his artistic competence. And however upsetting were many of Édouard Manet’s subjects, he certainly could capture a likeness. But many of Cezanne’s pictures are truly strange. Not an outsider, unlike Vincent van Gogh, he had a proper training. It’s true, thanks to his banker father, that fortunately he didn’t need to make a living from his art. And yet, if you set him alongside the Salon painters, then you can see how not just eccentric, but positively inept his art seemed to his contemporaries.

Nowadays I grant that only philistines call Cezanne inept or incompetent.

Nowadays, I grant that only philistines call Cezanne inept or incompetent. His apotheosis, along with the omnipresence of self-taught painters and consciously ‘bad art’ makes it difficult to understand this claim. Compared to Francis Bacon or Peter Saul, I grant, Cezanne is a model painter. But that present critical perspective in large part is a major cultural change, inspired in part by massive admiration for him. Many complex theories have been developed (by Roger Fry, Erle Loran, Meyer Schapiro, Maurice Merleau-Ponty and Richard Shiff) to explain why Cezanne’s paintings may look inept, but in fact are authentically expressive. And so it takes some historical perspective to understand their original strangeness. When some time ago the Musée d’Orsay was rehung to present sympathetically the Salon painters, that display was generally found uninspiring. Who, apart from a graduate student doing a doctoral thesis, responds to Thomas Couture? Cezanne’s status has become secure. On both days when I visited, this exhibition was crowded. What does this present almost universal admiration for Cezanne reveal, about our culture? Clark has a very well developed answer to this question. “We have a sense of ourselves as implicated in a world – reaching out to it, orienting ourselves to it, having it come (or not come) to where we are” (p. 110). That Clark’s Cézanne is a phenomenologist is unsurprising, for Maurice Merleau-Ponty’s famous essay “Cézanne’s doubt” popularized that claim. What, however, is more surprising is that Clark finds political implications in that role. “Cézanne’s unique way of being (pictorially) in the world” (pp. 147-8) ultimately revealed that “modernity (involves) loss of world” (p. 62).

In making these claims Clark is a ‘formalist.’ By that often controversial word, I allude to what’s been called in philosophy the synthesis of the manifold in perception. That is, just as philosophers discuss how we organize experience from sense impressions, so Clark’s interested in how the objects in Cezanne ’s pictures are put together, and not primarily in the artist’s highly personal choice of subjects. Edouard Manet’s still life subjects include oysters, plums, and salmon. No such luxury goods for Cezanne. And so it’s reasonable to ask why he sticks to his humble apples. Clark does have an extended discussion relating the fabrics in the still lives to Marx’s account of commodification. In the nineteenth century, Clark argues, human relationships with others were mediated by objects, in a way that was fictive. (This was fetishism.) But his discussion of alienation in industrial capitalism, which is a very familiar topic, doesn’t tell us much about Cézanne’s chosen subjects. What’s authentic about Cezanne, if I understand Clark’s account, was that he was the artist who best depicted this capitalist worldview. Cezanne’s paintings provide such a good image of nineteenth-century capitalism precisely because they do not depict factories, workers or the actual products of industrial production. For Clark, it’s the form of Cezanne’s paintings, and not their content, that demands a materialistic formalist analysis. How these paintings are put together has, he claims, political implications.

There is nothing wrong with formalism—not for me.

There is nothing wrong with formalism—not for me. When, however, Clark writes, “the word ‘Bloomsbury’ is my least favorite in the language” (p. 117), then you can sense his ambivalence about this analysis, for he does repeatedly argue at length and great sympathy with Roger Fry. And when he goes on to treat Cezanne as an aesthetic painter, then you sense his admirable willingness to be challenged and enchanted by these artworks that he loves. He doesn’t name ‘Heidegger’ when he says “The picture is the world we are in” (p. 223), but that’s one source, I suspect, of his account. Clark is concerned to explain how Cezanne’s landscapes are composed, without discussing the ownership of these sites. But since English leftist historians have discussed the ownership of the landscapes of Thomas Gainsborough and John Constable, might it not be instructive to ask who possessed and who worked these French lands? Many Marxists, including Clark himself, are fascinated by the urban subjects of the Impressionists. And it’s natural to ask, as he doesn’t, why Cezanne generally avoided showing city scenes. Paris Rooftops (1882), one exception, devotes a large part of the painting to depicting the banal rhythms of the rooftop, a subject worth of Sean Scully. But generally Cezanne shows very little interest in the modern city, or in industrialization. Clark-the-formalist doesn’t deal with that concern.

The account of present day politics in Afflicted Powers. Capital and Spectacle in a New Age of War, a book that was co-authored by Clark, also is in one way a formal account. This study of the politics of Islamic  struggles with the West, focused almost entirely on political forms of struggle, says almost nothing about specifically religious issues. In my judgment, that is an obviously strange omission. In the seventeenth-century, conflicts between the Ottomans and Europe were framed in religious terms. And so surely something of that tradition remains important, even if nowadays the European nations are essentially secular. Clark’s working assumption in both books, his account of Cezanne and Afflicted Powers, not really presented, much less defended in so many words, is that political concerns animate both Cezanne’s art and this thinking about 9/11.  Hence his critical claim:

Personal objects, including mass-produced objects, will necessarily go on being one main instrumentation of meaning and desiring in any human society we care to imagine. But they cannot and do not work the magic they are presently called on to perform (p. 179).

It would be worthwhile relating that claim made, as made in Afflicted Powers, to discussion of Cezanne’s still lives, for the unity of Clark’s thinking is important.

[1] Following the lead of the Société Paul Cezanne, as proposed by the artist’s great-grandson, the Tate identifies the artist previously know as ‘Paul Cézanne’ as ‘Paul Cezanne’, which was the original Provençal spelling of his name. I will follow that practice.

Note: This essay extends (incorporating some phrases, and at some places arguing with) my “Paul Cezanne-an Artist for Our Time,” (Counterpunch, 2023), and my review of T J Clark’s If These Apples Should Fall. Cézanne and the Present (British Journal of Aesthetics, 2022). The present analysis is anticipated by my review with Adele Tutter (Brooklyn Rail, 2015). On Retort see my “State of the Disunion: Hans Haacke and T.J.Clark,” ArtUS 12 (March-April 2006): 22-24. My quotation comes from Iain Boal, T. J. Clark, Joseph Matthews and Michael Watts (Retort), Afflicted Powers. Capital and Spectacle in a New Age of War (London, 2005). I owe my concept of artistic representation to Julian Bell, What is Painting? (2017). And Alex Danchev, Cézanne. A Life (2013) nicely supplements the Tate exhibition catalogue Cezanne.

Filed under Art History